Axiom









An axiom or postulate is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Greek axíōma (ἀξίωμα) 'that which is thought worthy or fit' or 'that which commends itself as evident.'[1][2]


The term has subtle differences in definition when used in the context of different fields of study. As defined in classic philosophy, an axiom is a statement that is so evident or well-established, that it is accepted without controversy or question.[3] As used in modern logic, an axiom is a premise or starting point for reasoning.[4]


As used in mathematics, the term axiom is used in two related but distinguishable senses: "logical axioms" and "non-logical axioms". Logical axioms are usually statements that are taken to be true within the system of logic they define (e.g., (A and B) implies A), often shown in symbolic form, while non-logical axioms (e.g., a + b = b + a) are actually substantive assertions about the elements of the domain of a specific mathematical theory (such as arithmetic). When used in the latter sense, "axiom", "postulate", and "assumption" may be used interchangeably. In general, a non-logical axiom is not a self-evident truth, but rather a formal logical expression used in deduction to build a mathematical theory. To axiomatize a system of knowledge is to show that its claims can be derived from a small, well-understood set of sentences (the axioms). There are typically multiple ways to axiomatize a given mathematical domain.


Any axiom is a statement that serves as a starting point from which other statements are logically derived. Whether it is meaningful (and, if so, what it means) for an axiom to be "true" is a subject of debate in the philosophy of mathematics.[5]




Contents






  • 1 Etymology


  • 2 Historical development


    • 2.1 Early Greeks


    • 2.2 Modern development


    • 2.3 Other sciences




  • 3 Mathematical logic


    • 3.1 Logical axioms


      • 3.1.1 Examples


        • 3.1.1.1 Propositional logic


        • 3.1.1.2 First-order logic






    • 3.2 Non-logical axioms


      • 3.2.1 Examples


        • 3.2.1.1 Arithmetic


        • 3.2.1.2 Euclidean geometry


        • 3.2.1.3 Real analysis






    • 3.3 Role in mathematical logic


      • 3.3.1 Deductive systems and completeness




    • 3.4 Further discussion




  • 4 See also


  • 5 References


  • 6 Further reading


  • 7 External links





Etymology


The word axiom comes from the Greek word ἀξίωμα (axíōma), a verbal noun from the verb ἀξιόειν (axioein), meaning "to deem worthy", but also "to require", which in turn comes from ἄξιος (áxios), meaning "being in balance", and hence "having (the same) value (as)", "worthy", "proper". Among the ancient Greek philosophers an axiom was a claim which could be seen to be true without any need for proof.


The root meaning of the word postulate is to "demand"; for instance, Euclid demands that one agree that some things can be done, e.g. any two points can be joined by a straight line, etc.[6]


Ancient geometers maintained some distinction between axioms and postulates. While commenting on Euclid's books, Proclus remarks that, "Geminus held that this [4th] Postulate should not be classed as a postulate but as an axiom, since it does not, like the first three Postulates, assert the possibility of some construction but expresses an essential property."[7]Boethius translated 'postulate' as petitio and called the axioms notiones communes but in later manuscripts this usage was not always strictly kept.



Historical development



Early Greeks


The logico-deductive method whereby conclusions (new knowledge) follow from premises (old knowledge) through the application of sound arguments (syllogisms, rules of inference), was developed by the ancient Greeks, and has become the core principle of modern mathematics. Tautologies excluded, nothing can be deduced if nothing is assumed. Axioms and postulates are the basic assumptions underlying a given body of deductive knowledge. They are accepted without demonstration. All other assertions (theorems, if we are talking about mathematics) must be proven with the aid of these basic assumptions. However, the interpretation of mathematical knowledge has changed from ancient times to the modern, and consequently the terms axiom and postulate hold a slightly different meaning for the present day mathematician, than they did for Aristotle and Euclid.


The ancient Greeks considered geometry as just one of several sciences, and held the theorems of geometry on par with scientific facts. As such, they developed and used the logico-deductive method as a means of avoiding error, and for structuring and communicating knowledge. Aristotle's posterior analytics is a definitive exposition of the classical view.



An "axiom", in classical terminology, referred to a self-evident assumption common to many branches of science. A good example would be the assertion that


When an equal amount is taken from equals, an equal amount results.


At the foundation of the various sciences lay certain additional hypotheses which were accepted without proof. Such a hypothesis was termed a postulate. While the axioms were common to many sciences, the postulates of each particular science were different. Their validity had to be established by means of real-world experience. Indeed, Aristotle warns that the content of a science cannot be successfully communicated, if the learner is in doubt about the truth of the postulates.[8]


The classical approach is well-illustrated by Euclid's Elements, where a list of postulates is given (common-sensical geometric facts drawn from our experience), followed by a list of "common notions" (very basic, self-evident assertions).



Postulates


  1. It is possible to draw a straight line from any point to any other point.

  2. It is possible to extend a line segment continuously in both directions.

  3. It is possible to describe a circle with any center and any radius.

  4. It is true that all right angles are equal to one another.

  5. ("Parallel postulate") It is true that, if a straight line falling on two straight lines make the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, the two straight lines, if produced indefinitely, intersect on that side on which are the angles less than the two right angles.





Common notions




  1. Things which are equal to the same thing are also equal to one another.

  2. If equals are added to equals, the wholes are equal.

  3. If equals are subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal.

  4. Things which coincide with one another are equal to one another.

  5. The whole is greater than the part.




Modern development


A lesson learned by mathematics in the last 150 years is that it is useful to strip the meaning away from the mathematical assertions (axioms, postulates, propositions, theorems) and definitions. One must concede the need for primitive notions, or undefined terms or concepts, in any study. Such abstraction or formalization makes mathematical knowledge more general, capable of multiple different meanings, and therefore useful in multiple contexts. Alessandro Padoa, Mario Pieri, and Giuseppe Peano were pioneers in this movement.


Structuralist mathematics goes further, and develops theories and axioms (e.g. field theory, group theory, topology, vector spaces) without any particular application in mind. The distinction between an "axiom" and a "postulate" disappears. The postulates of Euclid are profitably motivated by saying that they lead to a great wealth of geometric facts. The truth of these complicated facts rests on the acceptance of the basic hypotheses. However, by throwing out Euclid's fifth postulate we get theories that have meaning in wider contexts, hyperbolic geometry for example. We must simply be prepared to use labels like "line" and "parallel" with greater flexibility. The development of hyperbolic geometry taught mathematicians that postulates should be regarded as purely formal statements, and not as facts based on experience.


When mathematicians employ the field axioms, the intentions are even more abstract. The propositions of field theory do not concern any one particular application; the mathematician now works in complete abstraction. There are many examples of fields; field theory gives correct knowledge about them all.


It is not correct to say that the axioms of field theory are "propositions that are regarded as true without proof." Rather, the field axioms are a set of constraints. If any given system of addition and multiplication satisfies these constraints, then one is in a position to instantly know a great deal of extra information about this system.


Modern mathematics formalizes its foundations to such an extent that mathematical theories can be regarded as mathematical objects, and mathematics itself can be regarded as a branch of logic. Frege, Russell, Poincaré, Hilbert, and Gödel are some of the key figures in this development.


In the modern understanding, a set of axioms is any collection of formally stated assertions from which other formally stated assertions follow by the application of certain well-defined rules. In this view, logic becomes just another formal system. A set of axioms should be consistent; it should be impossible to derive a contradiction from the axiom. A set of axioms should also be non-redundant; an assertion that can be deduced from other axioms need not be regarded as an axiom.


It was the early hope of modern logicians that various branches of mathematics, perhaps all of mathematics, could be derived from a consistent collection of basic axioms. An early success of the formalist program was Hilbert's formalization of Euclidean geometry, and the related demonstration of the consistency of those axioms.


In a wider context, there was an attempt to base all of mathematics on Cantor's set theory. Here the emergence of Russell's paradox, and similar antinomies of naïve set theory raised the possibility that any such system could turn out to be inconsistent.


The formalist project suffered a decisive setback, when in 1931 Gödel showed that it is possible, for any sufficiently large set of axioms (Peano's axioms, for example) to construct a statement whose truth is independent of that set of axioms. As a corollary, Gödel proved that the consistency of a theory like Peano arithmetic is an unprovable assertion within the scope of that theory.


It is reasonable to believe in the consistency of Peano arithmetic because it is satisfied by the system of natural numbers, an infinite but intuitively accessible formal system. However, at present, there is no known way of demonstrating the consistency of the modern Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms for set theory. Furthermore, using techniques of forcing (Cohen) one can show that the continuum hypothesis (Cantor) is independent of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms. Thus, even this very general set of axioms cannot be regarded as the definitive foundation for mathematics.



Other sciences


Axioms play a key role not only in mathematics, but also in other sciences, notably in theoretical physics. In particular, the monumental work of Isaac Newton is essentially based on Euclid's axioms, augmented by a postulate on the non-relation of spacetime and the physics taking place in it at any moment.


In 1905, Newton's axioms were replaced by those of Albert Einstein's special relativity, and later on by those of general relativity.


Another paper of Albert Einstein and coworkers (see EPR paradox), almost immediately contradicted by Niels Bohr, concerned the interpretation of quantum mechanics. This was in 1935. According to Bohr, this new theory should be probabilistic, whereas according to Einstein it should be deterministic. Notably, the underlying quantum mechanical theory, i.e. the set of "theorems" derived by it, seemed to be identical. Einstein even assumed that it would be sufficient to add to quantum mechanics "hidden variables" to enforce determinism. However, thirty years later, in 1964, John Bell found a theorem, involving complicated optical correlations (see Bell inequalities), which yielded measurably different results using Einstein's axioms compared to using Bohr's axioms. And it took roughly another twenty years until an experiment of Alain Aspect got results in favour of Bohr's axioms, not Einstein's. (Bohr's axioms are simply: The theory should be probabilistic in the sense of the Copenhagen interpretation.)


As a consequence, it is not necessary to explicitly cite Einstein's axioms, the more so since they concern subtle points on the "reality" and "locality" of experiments.


Regardless, the role of axioms in mathematics and in the above-mentioned sciences is different. In mathematics one neither "proves" nor "disproves" an axiom for a set of theorems; the point is simply that in the conceptual realm identified by the axioms, the theorems logically follow. In contrast, in physics a comparison with experiments always makes sense, since a falsified physical theory needs modification.



Mathematical logic


In the field of mathematical logic, a clear distinction is made between two notions of axioms: logical and non-logical (somewhat similar to the ancient distinction between "axioms" and "postulates" respectively).



Logical axioms


These are certain formulas in a formal language that are universally valid, that is, formulas that are satisfied by every assignment of values. Usually one takes as logical axioms at least some minimal set of tautologies that is sufficient for proving all tautologies in the language; in the case of predicate logic more logical axioms than that are required, in order to prove logical truths that are not tautologies in the strict sense.



Examples



Propositional logic

In propositional logic it is common to take as logical axioms all formulae of the following forms, where ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi , χ{displaystyle chi }chi , and ψ{displaystyle psi }psi can be any formulae of the language and where the included primitive connectives are only "¬{displaystyle neg }neg " for negation of the immediately following proposition and "{displaystyle to }to " for implication from antecedent to consequent propositions:



  1. ϕϕ){displaystyle phi to (psi to phi )}phi to (psi to phi )

  2. χ))→((ϕψ)→χ)){displaystyle (phi to (psi to chi ))to ((phi to psi )to (phi to chi ))}(phi to (psi to chi ))to ((phi to psi )to (phi to chi ))

  3. ϕ¬ψ)→ϕ).{displaystyle (lnot phi to lnot psi )to (psi to phi ).}(lnot phi to lnot psi )to (psi to phi ).


Each of these patterns is an axiom schema, a rule for generating an infinite number of axioms. For example, if A{displaystyle A}A, B{displaystyle B}B, and C{displaystyle C}C are propositional variables, then A→(B→A){displaystyle Ato (Bto A)}Ato (Bto A) and (A→¬B)→(C→(A→¬B)){displaystyle (Ato lnot B)to (Cto (Ato lnot B))}(Ato lnot B)to (Cto (Ato lnot B)) are both instances of axiom schema 1, and hence are axioms. It can be shown that with only these three axiom schemata and modus ponens, one can prove all tautologies of the propositional calculus. It can also be shown that no pair of these schemata is sufficient for proving all tautologies with modus ponens.


Other axiom schemas involving the same or different sets of primitive connectives can be alternatively constructed.[9]


These axiom schemata are also used in the predicate calculus, but additional logical axioms are needed to include a quantifier in the calculus.[10]



First-order logic


Axiom of Equality. Let L{displaystyle {mathfrak {L}}}{mathfrak  {L}} be a first-order language. For each variable x{displaystyle x}x, the formula



x=x{displaystyle x=x}x = x



is universally valid.



This means that, for any variable symbol x,{displaystyle x,,}x,, the formula x=x{displaystyle x=x}x = x can be regarded as an axiom. Also, in this example, for this not to fall into vagueness and a never-ending series of "primitive notions", either a precise notion of what we mean by x=x{displaystyle x=x}x = x (or, for that matter, "to be equal") has to be well established first, or a purely formal and syntactical usage of the symbol ={displaystyle =}= has to be enforced, only regarding it as a string and only a string of symbols, and mathematical logic does indeed do that.


Another, more interesting example axiom scheme, is that which provides us with what is known as Universal Instantiation:



Axiom scheme for Universal Instantiation. Given a formula ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi in a first-order language L{displaystyle {mathfrak {L}}}{mathfrak  {L}}, a variable x{displaystyle x}x and a term t{displaystyle t}t that is substitutable for x{displaystyle x}x in ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi , the formula



ϕtx{displaystyle forall x,phi to phi _{t}^{x}}forall x,phi to phi _{t}^{x}



is universally valid.



Where the symbol ϕtx{displaystyle phi _{t}^{x}}phi _{t}^{x} stands for the formula ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi with the term t{displaystyle t}t substituted for x{displaystyle x}x. (See Substitution of variables.) In informal terms, this example allows us to state that, if we know that a certain property P{displaystyle P}P holds for every x{displaystyle x}x and that t{displaystyle t}t stands for a particular object in our structure, then we should be able to claim P(t){displaystyle P(t)}P(t). Again, we are claiming that the formula ϕtx{displaystyle forall xphi to phi _{t}^{x}}forall xphi to phi _{t}^{x} is valid, that is, we must be able to give a "proof" of this fact, or more properly speaking, a metaproof. Actually, these examples are metatheorems of our theory of mathematical logic since we are dealing with the very concept of proof itself. Aside from this, we can also have Existential Generalization:



Axiom scheme for Existential Generalization. Given a formula ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi in a first-order language L{displaystyle {mathfrak {L}}}{mathfrak  {L}}, a variable x{displaystyle x}x and a term t{displaystyle t}t that is substitutable for x{displaystyle x}x in ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi , the formula



ϕtx→{displaystyle phi _{t}^{x}to exists x,phi }phi _{t}^{x}to exists x,phi



is universally valid.




Non-logical axioms


Non-logical axioms are formulas that play the role of theory-specific assumptions. Reasoning about two different structures, for example the natural numbers and the integers, may involve the same logical axioms; the non-logical axioms aim to capture what is special about a particular structure (or set of structures, such as groups). Thus non-logical axioms, unlike logical axioms, are not tautologies. Another name for a non-logical axiom is postulate.[11]


Almost every modern mathematical theory starts from a given set of non-logical axioms, and it was thought[citation needed] that in principle every theory could be axiomatized in this way and formalized down to the bare language of logical formulas.


Non-logical axioms are often simply referred to as axioms in mathematical discourse. This does not mean that it is claimed that they are true in some absolute sense. For example, in some groups, the group operation is commutative, and this can be asserted with the introduction of an additional axiom, but without this axiom we can do quite well developing (the more general) group theory, and we can even take its negation as an axiom for the study of non-commutative groups.


Thus, an axiom is an elementary basis for a formal logic system that together with the rules of inference define a deductive system.



Examples


This section gives examples of mathematical theories that are developed entirely from a set of non-logical axioms (axioms, henceforth). A rigorous treatment of any of these topics begins with a specification of these axioms.


Basic theories, such as arithmetic, real analysis and complex analysis are often introduced non-axiomatically, but implicitly or explicitly there is generally an assumption that the axioms being used are the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with choice, abbreviated ZFC, or some very similar system of axiomatic set theory like Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory, a conservative extension of ZFC. Sometimes slightly stronger theories such as Morse–Kelley set theory or set theory with a strongly inaccessible cardinal allowing the use of a Grothendieck universe are used, but in fact most mathematicians can actually prove all they need in systems weaker than ZFC, such as second-order arithmetic.[citation needed]


The study of topology in mathematics extends all over through point set topology, algebraic topology, differential topology, and all the related paraphernalia, such as homology theory, homotopy theory. The development of abstract algebra brought with itself group theory, rings, fields, and Galois theory.


This list could be expanded to include most fields of mathematics, including measure theory, ergodic theory, probability, representation theory, and differential geometry.



Arithmetic

The Peano axioms are the most widely used axiomatization of first-order arithmetic. They are a set of axioms strong enough to prove many important facts about number theory and they allowed Gödel to establish his famous second incompleteness theorem.[12]


We have a language LNT={0,S}{displaystyle {mathfrak {L}}_{NT}={0,S}}{displaystyle {mathfrak {L}}_{NT}={0,S}} where 0{displaystyle 0}{displaystyle 0} is a constant symbol and S{displaystyle S}S is a unary function and the following axioms:



  1. x.¬(Sx=0){displaystyle forall x.lnot (Sx=0)}forall x.lnot (Sx=0)

  2. x.∀y.(Sx=Sy→x=y){displaystyle forall x.forall y.(Sx=Syto x=y)}forall x.forall y.(Sx=Syto x=y)


  3. (0)∧x.(ϕ(x)→ϕ(Sx)))→x.ϕ(x){displaystyle (phi (0)land forall x.,(phi (x)to phi (Sx)))to forall x.phi (x)}{displaystyle (phi (0)land forall x.,(phi (x)to phi (Sx)))to forall x.phi (x)} for any LNT{displaystyle {mathfrak {L}}_{NT}}{displaystyle {mathfrak {L}}_{NT}} formula ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi with one free variable.


The standard structure is N=⟨N,0,S⟩{displaystyle {mathfrak {N}}=langle mathbb {N} ,0,Srangle }{displaystyle {mathfrak {N}}=langle mathbb {N} ,0,Srangle } where N{displaystyle mathbb {N} }mathbb {N} is the set of natural numbers, S{displaystyle S}S is the successor function and 0{displaystyle 0}{displaystyle 0} is naturally interpreted as the number 0.



Euclidean geometry

Probably the oldest, and most famous, list of axioms are the 4 + 1 Euclid's postulates of plane geometry. The axioms are referred to as "4 + 1" because for nearly two millennia the fifth (parallel) postulate ("through a point outside a line there is exactly one parallel") was suspected of being derivable from the first four. Ultimately, the fifth postulate was found to be independent of the first four. Indeed, one can assume that exactly one parallel through a point outside a line exists, or that infinitely many exist. This choice gives us two alternative forms of geometry in which the interior angles of a triangle add up to exactly 180 degrees or less, respectively, and are known as Euclidean and hyperbolic geometries. If one also removes the second postulate ("a line can be extended indefinitely") then elliptic geometry arises, where there is no parallel through a point outside a line, and in which the interior angles of a triangle add up to more than 180 degrees.



Real analysis

The objectives of study are within the domain of real numbers. The real numbers are uniquely picked out (up to isomorphism) by the properties of a Dedekind complete ordered field, meaning that any nonempty set of real numbers with an upper bound has a least upper bound. However, expressing these properties as axioms requires use of second-order logic. The Löwenheim–Skolem theorems tell us that if we restrict ourselves to first-order logic, any axiom system for the reals admits other models, including both models that are smaller than the reals and models that are larger. Some of the latter are studied in non-standard analysis.



Role in mathematical logic



Deductive systems and completeness


A deductive system consists of a set Λ{displaystyle Lambda }Lambda of logical axioms, a set Σ{displaystyle Sigma }Sigma of non-logical axioms, and a set {(Γ)}{displaystyle {(Gamma ,phi )}}{displaystyle {(Gamma ,phi )}} of rules of inference. A desirable property of a deductive system is that it be complete. A system is said to be complete if, for all formulas ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi ,



if Σϕ then Σϕ{displaystyle {text{if }}Sigma models phi {text{ then }}Sigma vdash phi }{text{if }}Sigma models phi {text{ then }}Sigma vdash phi



that is, for any statement that is a logical consequence of Σ{displaystyle Sigma }Sigma there actually exists a deduction of the statement from Σ{displaystyle Sigma }Sigma . This is sometimes expressed as "everything that is true is provable", but it must be understood that "true" here means "made true by the set of axioms", and not, for example, "true in the intended interpretation". Gödel's completeness theorem establishes the completeness of a certain commonly used type of deductive system.


Note that "completeness" has a different meaning here than it does in the context of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem, which states that no recursive, consistent set of non-logical axioms Σ{displaystyle Sigma }Sigma of the Theory of Arithmetic is complete, in the sense that there will always exist an arithmetic statement ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi such that neither ϕ{displaystyle phi }phi nor ¬ϕ{displaystyle lnot phi }{displaystyle lnot phi } can be proved from the given set of axioms.


There is thus, on the one hand, the notion of completeness of a deductive system and on the other hand that of completeness of a set of non-logical axioms. The completeness theorem and the incompleteness theorem, despite their names, do not contradict one another.



Further discussion


Early mathematicians regarded axiomatic geometry as a model of physical space, and obviously there could only be one such model. The idea that alternative mathematical systems might exist was very troubling to mathematicians of the 19th century and the developers of systems such as Boolean algebra made elaborate efforts to derive them from traditional arithmetic. Galois showed just before his untimely death that these efforts were largely wasted. Ultimately, the abstract parallels between algebraic systems were seen to be more important than the details and modern algebra was born. In the modern view axioms may be any set of formulas, as long as they are not known to be inconsistent.



See also




  • Axiomatic system

  • Dogma

  • List of axioms

  • Model theory

  • Regulæ Juris

  • Theorem

  • Presupposition

  • Physical law

  • Axioms (journal)



References





  1. ^ Cf. axiom, n., etymology. Oxford English Dictionary, accessed 2012-04-28.


  2. ^ Oxford American College Dictionary: "n. a statement or proposition that is regarded as being established, accepted, or self-evidently true. ORIGIN: late 15th cent.: ultimately from Greek axiōma 'what is thought fitting,' from axios 'worthy.' http://www.highbeam.com/doc/1O997-axiom.html (subscription required)


  3. ^ "A proposition that commends itself to general acceptance; a well-established or universally conceded principle; a maxim, rule, law" axiom, n., definition 1a. Oxford English Dictionary Online, accessed 2012-04-28. Cf. Aristotle, Posterior Analytics I.2.72a18-b4.


  4. ^ "A proposition (whether true or false)" axiom, n., definition 2. Oxford English Dictionary Online, accessed 2012-04-28.


  5. ^ See for example Maddy, Penelope (Jun 1988). "Believing the Axioms, I". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 53 (2): 481–511. doi:10.2307/2274520..mw-parser-output cite.citation{font-style:inherit}.mw-parser-output q{quotes:"""""""'""'"}.mw-parser-output code.cs1-code{color:inherit;background:inherit;border:inherit;padding:inherit}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-free a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/65/Lock-green.svg/9px-Lock-green.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-limited a,.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-registration a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/d/d6/Lock-gray-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-gray-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-subscription a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/a/aa/Lock-red-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-red-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration{color:#555}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription span,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration span{border-bottom:1px dotted;cursor:help}.mw-parser-output .cs1-hidden-error{display:none;font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-visible-error{font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration,.mw-parser-output .cs1-format{font-size:95%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-left,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-left{padding-left:0.2em}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-right,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-right{padding-right:0.2em} for a realist view.


  6. ^ Wolff, P. Breakthroughs in Mathematics, 1963, New York: New American Library, pp 47–48


  7. ^ Heath, T. 1956. The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements. New York: Dover. p 200


  8. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics Bk IV, Chapter 3, 1005b "Physics also is a kind of Wisdom, but it is not the first kind. – And the attempts of some of those who discuss the terms on which truth should be accepted, are due to want of training in logic; for they should know these things already when they come to a special study, and not be inquiring into them while they are listening to lectures on it." W.D. Ross translation, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, (Random House, New York, 1941)|date=June 2011


  9. ^ Mendelson, "6. Other Axiomatizations" of Ch. 1


  10. ^ Mendelson, "3. First-Order Theories" of Ch. 2


  11. ^ Mendelson, "3. First-Order Theories: Proper Axioms" of Ch. 2


  12. ^ Mendelson, "5. The Fixed Point Theorem. Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem" of Ch. 2




Further reading



  • Mendelson, Elliot (1987). Introduction to mathematical logic. Belmont, California: Wadsworth & Brooks.
    ISBN 0-534-06624-0


  • Wilson, John Cook (1889). On an Evolutionist Theory of Axioms. Oxford: Clarendon Press.



External links












  • Axiom at PhilPapers


  • Axiom at PlanetMath.org.


  • Metamath axioms page









這個網誌中的熱門文章

12.7 cm/40 Type 89 naval gun

Rikitea

University of Vienna