Intentionality





Intentionality is a philosophical concept and is defined by the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy as "the power of minds to be about, to represent, or to stand for, things, properties and states of affairs".[1] The once obsolete term dates from medieval scholastic philosophy, but in more recent times it has been resurrected by Franz Brentano and adopted by Edmund Husserl. The earliest theory of intentionality is associated with St. Anselm's ontological argument for the existence of God, and with his tenets distinguishing between objects that exist in the understanding and objects that exist in reality.[2]




Contents






  • 1 Overview


  • 2 Dennett's taxonomy of current theories about intentionality


  • 3 Basic intentionality types according to Le Morvan


  • 4 Mental states without intentionality


    • 4.1 Intentionality and self-consciousness




  • 5 See also


  • 6 References


  • 7 Further reading


  • 8 External links





Overview


The concept of intentionality was reintroduced in 19th-century contemporary philosophy by Franz Brentano (a German philosopher and psychologist who is generally regarded as the founder of act psychology, also called intentionalism)[3] in his work Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (1874). Brentano described intentionality as a characteristic of all acts of consciousness that are thus "psychical" or "mental" phenomena, by which they may be set apart from "physical" or "natural" phenomena.


.mw-parser-output .templatequote{overflow:hidden;margin:1em 0;padding:0 40px}.mw-parser-output .templatequote .templatequotecite{line-height:1.5em;text-align:left;padding-left:1.6em;margin-top:0}

Every mental phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages called the intentional (or mental) inexistence of an object, and what we might call, though not wholly unambiguously, reference to a content, direction towards an object (which is not to be understood here as meaning a thing), or immanent objectivity. Every mental phenomenon includes something as object within itself, although they do not all do so in the same way. In presentation something is presented, in judgement something is affirmed or denied, in love loved, in hate hated, in desire desired and so on. This intentional in-existence is characteristic exclusively of mental phenomena. No physical phenomenon exhibits anything like it. We could, therefore, define mental phenomena by saying that they are those phenomena which contain an object intentionally within themselves.


— Franz Brentano, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, edited by Linda L. McAlister (London: Routledge, 1995), pp. 88–89.


Brentano coined the expression "intentional inexistence" to indicate the peculiar ontological status of the contents of mental phenomena. According to some interpreters the "in-" of "in-existence" is to be read as locative, i.e. as indicating that "an intended object ... exists in or has in-existence, existing not externally but in the psychological state" (Jacquette 2004, p. 102), while others are more cautious, stating: "It is not clear whether in 1874 this ... was intended to carry any ontological commitment" (Chrudzimski and Smith 2004, p. 205).


A major problem within discourse on intentionality is that participants often fail to make explicit whether or not they use the term to imply concepts such as agency or desire, i.e. whether it involves teleology. Dennett (see below) explicitly invokes teleological concepts in the "intentional stance". However, most philosophers use "intentionality" to mean something with no teleological import. Thus, a thought of a chair can be about a chair without any implication of an intention or even a belief relating to the chair. For philosophers of language, what is meant by intentionality is largely an issue of how symbols can have meaning. This lack of clarity may underpin some of the differences of view indicated below.


To bear out further the diversity of sentiment evoked from the notion of intentionality, Husserl followed on Brentano, and gave the concept of intentionality more widespread attention, both in continental and analytic philosophy.[4] In contrast to Brentano's view, French philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre (Being and Nothingness) identified intentionality with consciousness, stating that the two were indistinguishable.[5] German philosopher Martin Heidegger (Being and Time), defined intentionality as "care" (Sorge), a sentient condition where an individual's existence, facticity, and being in the world identifies their ontological significance, in contrast to that which is merely ontic ("thinghood").[6]


Other 20th-century philosophers such as Gilbert Ryle and A.J. Ayer were critical of Husserl's concept of intentionality and his many layers of consciousness.[7] Ryle insisted that perceiving is not a process,[8] and Ayer that describing one's knowledge is not to describe mental processes.[9] The effect of these positions is that consciousness is so fully intentional that the mental act has been emptied of all content, and that the idea of pure consciousness is that it is nothing.[10] (Sartre also referred to "consciousness" as "nothing").[11]


Platonist Roderick Chisholm has revived the Brentano thesis through linguistic analysis, distinguishing two parts to Brentano's concept, the ontological aspect and the psychological aspect.[12] Chisholm's writings have attempted to summarize the suitable and unsuitable criteria of the concept since the Scholastics, arriving at a criterion of intentionality identified by the two aspects of Brentano's thesis and defined by the logical properties that distinguish language describing psychological phenomena from language describing non-psychological phenomena.[13] Chisholm's criteria for the intentional use of sentences are: existence independence, truth-value indifference, and referential opacity.[14]


In current artificial intelligence and philosophy of mind, intentionality is sometimes linked with questions of semantic inference, with both skeptical and supportive adherents.[15]John Searle argued for this position with the Chinese room thought experiment, according to which no syntactic operations that occurred in a computer would provide it with semantic content.[16] Others are more skeptical of the human ability to make such an assertion, arguing that the kind of intentionality that emerges from self-organizing networks of automata will always be undecidable because it will never be possible to make our subjective introspective experience of intentionality and decision making coincide with our objective observation of the behavior of a self-organizing machine.[17]



Dennett's taxonomy of current theories about intentionality


Daniel Dennett offers a taxonomy of the current theories about intentionality in Chapter 10 of his book The Intentional Stance. Most, if not all, current theories on intentionality accept Brentano's thesis of the irreducibility of intentional idiom. From this thesis the following positions emerge:



  • intentional idiom is problematic for science;

  • intentional idiom is not problematic for science, which is divided into:


    • Eliminative Materialism;


    • Realism;

    • Quinean double standard (see below) which is divided into:

      • adherence to Normative Principle (epistemology), which is divided into:

        • who makes an Assumption of Rationality;

        • who follows the Principle of Charity;



      • adherence to Projective Principle.






Roderick Chisholm (1956), G.E.M. Anscombe (1957), Peter Geach (1957), and Charles Taylor (1964) all adhere to the former position, namely that intentional idiom is problematic and cannot be integrated with the natural sciences. Members of this category also maintain realism in regard to intentional objects, which may imply some kind of dualism (though this is debatable).


The latter position, which maintains the unity of intentionality with the natural sciences, is further divided into three standpoints:




  • Eliminative materialism, supported by W.V. Quine (1960) and Churchland (1981)


  • Realism, advocated by Jerry Fodor (1975), as well as Burge, Dretske, Kripke, and the early Hilary Putnam

  • those who adhere to the Quinean double standard.


Proponents of the eliminative materialism, understand intentional idiom, such as "belief", "desire", and the like, to be replaceable either with behavioristic language (e.g. Quine) or with the language of neuroscience (e.g. Churchland).


Holders of realism argue that there is a deeper fact of the matter to both translation and belief attribution. In other words, manuals for translating one language into another cannot be set up in different yet behaviorally identical ways and ontologically there are intentional objects. Famously, Fodor has attempted to ground such realist claims about intentionality in a language of thought. Dennett comments on this issue, Fodor "attempt[s] to make these irreducible realities acceptable to the physical sciences by grounding them (somehow) in the 'syntax' of a system of physically realized mental representations" (Dennett 1987, 345).


Those who adhere to the so-called Quinean double standard (namely that ontologically there is nothing intentional, but that the language of intentionality is indispensable), accept Quine's thesis of the indeterminacy of radical translation and its implications, while the other positions so far mentioned do not. As Quine puts it, indeterminacy of radical translation is the thesis that "manuals for translating one language into another can be set up in divergent ways, all compatible with the totality of speech dispositions, yet incompatible with one another" (Quine 1960, 27). Quine (1960) and Wilfrid Sellars (1958) both comment on this intermediary position. One such implication would be that there is, in principle, no deeper fact of the matter that could settle two interpretative strategies on what belief to attribute to a physical system. In other words, the behavior (including speech dispositions) of any physical system, in theory, could be interpreted by two different predictive strategies and both would be equally warranted in their belief attribution. This category can be seen to be a medial position between the realists and the eliminativists since it attempts to blend attributes of both into a theory of intentionality. Dennett, for example, argues in True Believers (1981) that intentional idiom (or "folk psychology") is a predictive strategy and if such a strategy successfully and voluminously predicts the actions of a physical system, then that physical system can be said to have those beliefs attributed to it. Dennett calls this predictive strategy the intentional stance.


They are further divided into two theses:



  • adherence to the Normative Principle

  • adherence to the Projective Principle


Advocates of the former, the Normative Principle, argue that attributions of intentional idioms to physical systems should be the propositional attitudes that the physical system ought to have in those circumstances (Dennett 1987, 342). However, exponents of this view are still further divided into those who make an Assumption of Rationality and those who adhere to the Principle of Charity. Dennett (1969, 1971, 1975), Cherniak (1981, 1986), and the more recent work of Putnam (1983) recommend the Assumption of Rationality, which unsurprisingly assumes that the physical system in question is rational. Donald Davidson (1967, 1973, 1974, 1985) and Lewis (1974) defend the Principle of Charity.


The latter is advocated by Grandy (1973) and Stich (1980, 1981, 1983, 1984), who maintain that attributions of intentional idioms to any physical system (e.g. humans, artifacts, non-human animals, etc.) should be the propositional attitude (e.g. "belief", "desire", etc.) that one would suppose one would have in the same circumstances (Dennett 1987, 343).



Basic intentionality types according to Le Morvan


Working on the intentionality of vision, belief, and knowledge, Pierre Le Morvan (2005)[18] has distinguished between three basic kinds of intentionality that he dubs "transparent", "translucent", and "opaque" respectively. The threefold distinction may be explained as follows. Let's call the "intendum" what an intentional state is about, and the "intender" the subject who is in the intentional state. An intentional state is transparent if it satisfies the following two conditions: (i) it is genuinely relational in that it entails the existence of not just the intender but the intendum as well, and (ii) substitutivity of identicals applies to the intendum (i.e. if the intentional state is about a, and a = b, then the intentional state is about b as well). An intentional state is translucent if it satisfies (i) but not (ii). An intentional state is opaque if it satisfies neither (i) nor (ii).



Mental states without intentionality


The claim that all mental states are intentional is called intentionalism, the contrary being anti-intentionalism.


Some anti-intentionalism, such as that of Ned Block, is based on the argument that phenomenal conscious experience or qualia is also a vital component of consciousness, and that it is not intentional. (The latter claim is itself disputed by Michael Tye.)[19]


Another form of anti-intentionalism associated with John Searle regards phenomenality itself as the "mark of the mental" and sidelines intentionality.[20]


A further form argues that some unusual states of consciousness are non-intentional, although an individual might live a lifetime without experiencing them. Robert K.C. Forman argues that some of the unusual states of consciousness typical of mystical experience are pure consciousness events in which awareness exists, but has no object, is not awareness "of" anything.



Intentionality and self-consciousness


Several authors have attempted to construct philosophical models describing how intentionality relates to the human capacity to be self-conscious. Cedric Evans contributed greatly to the discussion with his "The Subject of Self-Consciousness" in 1970. He centered his model on the idea that executive attention need not be propositional in form.[21]



See also












References





  1. ^ Jacob, P. (Aug 31, 2010). "Intentionality". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 December 2012..mw-parser-output cite.citation{font-style:inherit}.mw-parser-output q{quotes:"""""""'""'"}.mw-parser-output code.cs1-code{color:inherit;background:inherit;border:inherit;padding:inherit}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-free a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/65/Lock-green.svg/9px-Lock-green.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-limited a,.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-registration a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/d/d6/Lock-gray-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-gray-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-subscription a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/a/aa/Lock-red-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-red-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration{color:#555}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription span,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration span{border-bottom:1px dotted;cursor:help}.mw-parser-output .cs1-hidden-error{display:none;font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-visible-error{font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration,.mw-parser-output .cs1-format{font-size:95%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-left,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-left{padding-left:0.2em}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-right,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-right{padding-right:0.2em}


  2. ^ Chisholm, Roderick M. (1967). "Intentionality". The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 4: 201.


  3. ^ Franz Brentano – Britannica.com


  4. ^ Smith, David Woodruff. Husserl. New York: Routledge. p. 10. ISBN 0-415-28974-2.


  5. ^ Jean-Paul Sartre (2012). Being and Nothingness. Open Road Media. ISBN 1453228551.


  6. ^ Martin Heidegger (1967). Being and Time. John Wiley & Sons. p. 84. ISBN 0631197702.


  7. ^ Ayer, A.J. (1984). More of My Life. New York: HarperCollins. p. 26. ISBN 0-19-281878-3.


  8. ^ Locke, Don (2002). Perception: And Our Knowledge Of The External World, Volume 3. London: Routledge. p. 28. ISBN 0-415-29562-9.


  9. ^ Macdonald, Graham. "Alfred Jules Ayer". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP). Metaphysics Research Lab, CSLI, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 December 2012.


  10. ^ Siewert, Charles. "Consciousness and Intentionality". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP). Metaphysics Research Lab, CSLI, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 December 2012.


  11. ^ Franchi, Leo. "Sartre and Freedom" (PDF). Retrieved 28 December 2012.


  12. ^ Byrne, Alex. "Intentionality". Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Retrieved 28 December 2012.


  13. ^ Bechtel, William (1988). Philosophy of Mind: An Overview for Cognitive Science. Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum. pp. 44–47. ISBN 978-0805802214.


  14. ^ Horosz, William and Tad S. Clements (1986). Religion and Human Purpose: A Cross Disciplinary Approach. New York: Springer. p. 35. ISBN 978-9024730001.


  15. ^ "Might the Singularity never occur?". Singularity FAQ. Singularity Institute. Retrieved 28 December 2012.


  16. ^ Marconi, Diego (1996). "On the Referential Competence of Some Machines", in Integration of Natural Language and Vision Processing: Theory and Grounding Representations, Volume 3, edited by Paul Mc Kevitt. New York: Springer. p. 31. ISBN 978-9401072335.


  17. ^ Atlan, H. (1991). "Ends and Means in Machine-Like Systems", in New Perspectives on Cybernetics: Self-Organization, Autonomy and Connectionism, edited by Gertrudis Van de Vijver. New York: Sringer. p. 39. ISBN 978-9048141074.


  18. ^ Pierre Le Morvan (2005). "Intentionality: Transparent, Translucent, And Opaque" (PDF). Journal of Philosophical Research. 30: 283–302. doi:10.5840/jpr20053039. Retrieved 21 December 2012.


  19. ^ Michael Tye (1995). "A Representational Theory of Pains and their Phenomenal Character". Philosophical Perspectives. 9: 223–39. doi:10.2307/2214219. Retrieved 21 December 2012. [T]he phenomenal character of my pain intuitively is something that is given to me via introspection of what I experience in having the pain. But what I experience is what my experience represents. So, phenomenal character is representational.


  20. ^ Pierre Jacob (Aug 31, 2010). "Is intentionality exhibited by all mental phenomena?". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 December 2012.


  21. ^ C.O. Evans (1970). "The Subject of Consciousness". Mental States. Retrieved 21 December 2012.




Further reading



  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957, second edition 1963) Intention. Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
    ISBN 978-0-6740-0399-6

  • Brentano, Franz (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte Leipzig, Duncker & Humblot (Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, Routledge, 1973).

  • Chisholm, Roderick M. (1967). "Intentionality" in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Macmillan.
    ISBN 978-0-02-894990-1

  • Chisholm, Roderick M. (1963). "Notes on the Logic of Believing" in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. 24: p. 195-201. Reprinted in Marras, Ausonio. Ed. (1972) Intentionality, mind, and language.
    ISBN 0-252-00211-3

  • Chisholm, Roderick M. (1957). Perceiving: A Philosophical Study. Cornell University Press.
    ISBN 978-0-8014-0077-3

  • Chrudzimski, Arkadiusz and Barry Smith (2004) "Brentano’s Ontology: from Conceptualism to Reism" in Jacquette (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Brentano
    ISBN 0-521-00765-8

  • Davidson, Donald. "Truth and Meaning". Synthese, XVII, pp. 304–23. 1967.

  • Dennett, Daniel C. (1989). The Intentional Stance. The MIT Press.
    ISBN 978-0-262-54053-7

  • Dreyfus, Georges. "Is Perception Intentional? (A Preliminary Exploration of Intentionality in Indian Philosophy)." 2006.

  • Fodor, J. "The Language of Thought". Harvard University Press. 1980.
    ISBN 0-674-51030-5

  • Husserl, Edmund (1962). Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Collier Books.
    ISBN 978-0-415-29544-4

  • Husserl, Edmund. Logical Investigations.
    ISBN 978-1-57392-866-3

  • Jacquette, Dale (2004) "Brentano’s Concept of Intentionality" in Jacquette (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Brentano
    ISBN 0-521-00765-8

  • Le Morvan, Pierre (2005). "Intentionality: Transparent, Translucent, and Opaque". The Journal of Philosophical Research, 30, p. 283-302.

  • Malle, B. F., Moses, L. J., & Baldwin, D. A. (Eds.) (2003). Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition. The MIT Press.
    ISBN 978-0-262-63267-6.

  • Mohanty, Jitendra Nath (1972). The Concept of Intentionality: A Critical Study. St. Louis, MO: Warren H. Green, 1972.
    ISBN 978-0-87527-115-6


  • Padilla Gálvez, J., M. Gaffal (eds.), Intentionality and Action. De Gruyter, Berlin - Boston, 2017.
    ISBN 978-3-11-056028-2. [1]

  • Perler, Dominik (ed.) (2001), Ancient and Medieval Theories of Internationality, Leiden, Brill.
    ISBN 978-9-00412-295-6

  • Quine, W.V. (1960). Word and Object. The MIT Press.
    ISBN 978-0-262-67001-2.

  • Sajama, Seppo & Kamppinen, Matti. Historical Introduction to Phenomenology. New York, NY: Croom Helm, 1987.
    ISBN 0-7099-4443-8

  • Stich, Stephen. "Relativism, Rationality, and the Limits of Intentional Description". Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 65, pp. 211–35. 1984.

  • Williford, Kenneth. "The Intentionality of Consciousness and Consciousness of Intentionality. In G. Forrai and G. Kampis, eds., Intentionality: Past and Future. Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 143–156. 2005.
    ISBN 90-420-1817-8



External links



  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:

    • Intentionality

    • Consciousness and Intentionality

    • Ancient Theories of Intentionality



  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:

    • Intentionality

    • Collective Intentionality











這個網誌中的熱門文章

12.7 cm/40 Type 89 naval gun

Rikitea

University of Vienna